HomeGroupsTalkMoreZeitgeist
Search Site
This site uses cookies to deliver our services, improve performance, for analytics, and (if not signed in) for advertising. By using LibraryThing you acknowledge that you have read and understand our Terms of Service and Privacy Policy. Your use of the site and services is subject to these policies and terms.

Results from Google Books

Click on a thumbnail to go to Google Books.

Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life…
Loading...

Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life (Meridian: Crossing Aesthetics) (original 1995; edition 1998)

by Giorgio Agamben

Series: Homo Sacer (I)

MembersReviewsPopularityAverage ratingMentions
1,014920,371 (3.97)4
The work of Giorgio Agamben, one of Italy's most important and original philosophers, has been based on an uncommon erudition in classical traditions of philosophy and rhetoric, the grammarians of late antiquity, Christian theology, and modern philosophy. Recently, Agamben has begun to direct his thinking to the constitution of the social and to some concrete, ethico-political conclusions concerning the state of society today, and the place of the individual within it. In Homo Sacer, Agamben aims to connect the problem of pure possibility, potentiality, and power with the problem of political and social ethics in a context where the latter has lost its previous religious, metaphysical, and cultural grounding. Taking his cue from Foucault's fragmentary analysis of biopolitics, Agamben probes with great breadth, intensity, and acuteness the covert or implicit presence of an idea of biopolitics in the history of traditional political theory. He argues that from the earliest treatises of political theory, notably in Aristotle's notion of man as a political animal, and throughout the history of Western thinking about sovereignty (whether of the king or the state), a notion of sovereignty as power over "life" is implicit. The reason it remains merely implicit has to do, according to Agamben, with the way the sacred, or the idea of sacrality, becomes indissociable from the idea of sovereignty. Drawing upon Carl Schmitt's idea of the sovereign's status as the exception to the rules he safeguards, and on anthropological research that reveals the close interlinking of the sacred and the taboo, Agamben defines the sacred person as one who can be killed and yet not sacrificed--a paradox he sees as operative in the status of the modern individual living in a system that exerts control over the collective "naked life" of all individuals.… (more)
Member:Friedrich.Stromeyer
Title:Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life (Meridian: Crossing Aesthetics)
Authors:Giorgio Agamben
Info:Stanford University Press (1998), Paperback, 211 pages
Collections:Your library
Rating:*****
Tags:sovreign-inflation

Work Information

Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life by Giorgio Agamben (1995)

Loading...

Sign up for LibraryThing to find out whether you'll like this book.

No current Talk conversations about this book.

» See also 4 mentions

English (7)  French (1)  Spanish (1)  All languages (9)
Showing 1-5 of 7 (next | show all)
The concept of Homo Sacer, taken from the ancient Roman code, is a marginal existence excluded by both divine law and human law.

Through the allusion of homo sacer, Agamben reinterprets the paradox of "Biopolitique" in modern society and its historical origin (continuing on the basis of Foucault's "Biopolitique"). Before the introduction of "Homo Sacer", Agamben made an important classification of life management -- formal life (bios) and naked life (zoe). The combination of zoe and bios is that zoe in the private domain is pulled into the public domain and thus managed by the modern ruling body. Agamben introduced the concept of "homo sacer", which is special in that it is included in the city state in an excluded form, reflecting the most complete form of naked life, and the construction of the social normality that Foucault worried about can be traced back to a long time ago.

One of the most peculiar points of Agamben's argument: There is an inescapable dilemma in modern society, another aspect of the management of life can be eliminated for the same reason, and democracy, which is divided into the opposite of totalitarianism, is also in fact in the logic of the management of life with the enemy, especially through the suspension of the law by the "state of exception", the sovereign with the right to dispose of life and death will re-emerge. This is the most important addition to Foucault's argument.
  Maristot | Jul 29, 2023 |
“Sovereign violence is in truth founded not on a pact but on the exclusive inclusion of bare life in the state."
For a certain class of reader (myself not excepted) Agamben is a better instructor on Hegel than the Phenomenology. Agamben's demonstration of the state of the Sacred as dialectical synthesis of example-exception in the first part of this text is illuminating. The example is excluded precisely as it is set aside from the group to be used as an example – inversely for the exclusion. His discussion of the application of the Law, although appearing to draw heavily from Foucault, is a similarly interesting:
"Just as the law, in the sovereign exception, applies to the exceptional case in no longer applying and in withdrawing from it, so homo sacer belongs to G-d in the form of unsacrificeability and is included in the community in the form of being able to be killed. "
To a lesser extent this Hegelian turn is also applied in the very first sections, which elaborate Sovereign power as that which exists outside the law and declares that nothing is outside the law, but is only able to make this claim because the sovereign is outside it. (In a return to Aquinas’s proofs he has demonstrated that in order to posit the Law (creation), the sovereign (G-d) must first exist outside it.)

Agamben’s discussion on the Creation of the Law is also remarkable in that it proceeds backwards from effects to causes. Per Agamben, its genesis consists precisely in the an act of violence in exception to the normal state of affairs. Only the systematic application of this violence to the extent that it forms a pattern could be called the means of creation of the Law which cobbles its name in retrospect. The function of the law is also inverted – not negative injunction and “not the act of tracing boundaries, but their cancellation or negation is the constitutive act of the city (and this is what the myth of the foundation of Rome, after all, teaches with perfect clarity). […] The original political relation is the ban (the state of exception as zone of indistinction between outside and inside, exclusion and inclusion).”

His discussion of Nature goes beyond the critical dichotomies of historical-nature and natural-history, and this might be the truest section of the piece.
“We have seen that the state of nature is not a real epoch chronologically prior to the foundation of the City but a principle internal to the City, which appears at the moment the City is considered tanquam dissoluta, […] but what then appears is in fact not the state of nature (as an earlier stage into which men would fall back) but the state of exception. The state of nature and the state of exception are nothing but two sides of a single topological process in which what was presupposed as external (the state of nature) now reappears in the inside.”
The discussion on Kafka's "Before the Law' (section of The Trial) is an entertaining application of "Theory" toward the reversal of dusty canonical interpretations, though the exegetical reverence for Kafka's works as of biblical parables is tiresome (not Agamben's fault the literati love this dude).
"The interpreters seem to forget, in fact, precisely the words with which the story ends: "No one else could enter here, since this door was destined for you alone. Now I will go and shut it." If it is true the door's very openness constituted, as we saw, the invisible power and specific "force" of the Law, then we can imagine that all the behavior of the man from the country is nothing other than a complicated and patient strategy to have the door closed in order to interrupt the Law's being in force. And in the end, the man succeeds in his endeavor, since he succeeds in having the door of the Law closed forever "
Yet everything proceeds too easily. Agamben is taking some liberties (his sovereign right for creating this work). Contrast the authoritative English translation of Benjamin’s VIII Thesis on the Philosophy of History with Agamben’s: Instead of "… state of emergency in which we live ... it is our task to bring about a real state of emergency," we find, "… state of exception in which we live. Then we will have the production of the real state of exception before us as a task." Agamben appears to be Breaking Benjamin, upon whose concept of “Bare Life” this work seems to depend.

Agamben also transgresses a boundary in his discussion of brain death. He appears to make one of the classic rhetorical blunders, using ‘obviously’ to describe a statement in which he has the least certainty:
“The hospital room in which the neomort, the overcomatose person, and the faux vivantwaver between life and death delimits a space of exception in which a purely bare life, entirely controlled by man and his technology, appears for the first time. […] What is at stake is, once again, the definition of a life that may be killed without the commission of homicide (and that is, like homo sacer, "unsacrificeable," in the sense that it obviously could not be put to death following a death sentence)."
Rather than the epitome of “Homo Sacer”, “Coma Depasse/Deep Coma” appears to be precisely the inverse: a body in the state of exception which cannot be killed but can be sacrificed. The Deep Coma patient cannot be killed except by strictly-prescribed ritual i.e. "pulling the plug" or "live-organ harvesting". The application of the death sentence would not be inappropriate as it now occurs by the same medicated rituals as the organ harvesting process. The death sentence, where it still exists in the united states, is already separated from the notion of the exercise of capricious sovereign power upon bare life. No longer functioning in the service of a concept of deterrence or public safety it and now struggles along purely as sacrificial rite – (open to discussion). In fact, the overcomatose patient is precisely the person for whom the death sentence would be most appropriate. Conversely, the idea of stabbing such a person to death is inconceivable (they are already dead and thus cannot be killed).

Most significantly, Agamben returns to another proof of Aquinas (Argument from Degree) to support the strongest impacts of his work i.e. there exists a state of greatest realization of biopolitics and we might therefore call this state the epitome of the ‘modern’  the State of Exception as a unique feature of modern societies is therefore their defining quality and such States will soon extend over the entire planet:
"What is happening in ex-Yugoslavia and, more generally, what is happening in the processes of dissolution of traditional State organisms in Eastern Europe should be viewed not as a reemergence of the natural state of struggle of all against all-which functions as a prelude to new social contracts and new national and State localizations but rather as the coming to light of the state of exception as the permanent structure of juridico-political de-localization and dis-location. Political organization is not regressing toward outdated forms; rather, premonitory events are, like bloody masses, announcing the new nomos of the earth, which (if its grounding principle is not called into question) will soon extend itself over the entire planet."
I don’t trust this conclusion for a couple reasons. First, might it not just as readily turn out otherwise? The Biopolitical “Argument from Degree” has its share of proponents, yet one is reminded of the Marxist declaration on the unsustainability of the capitalist system, the end of which has not quite yet arrived although they have in its stead devised a series of pejorative terms "late/end-stage capitalism" and now “neoliberalism". I might interject, "The market can remain irrational longer than you can remain solvent,” &c. Second, if the state of exception exists in “zones d'attentes in French international airports”, then "the state of exception as a modern phenomenon does not exist, because it has always existed” in the exclusive-inclusion of the refugee camp and leper colony/ghetto within the city gates.

Finally, instead of the Camp, one might more accurately posit the State of Staring-At-Your-Phone (SAYP) as the epitome of the modern. To its credit, SAYP has already succeeded in extended over the entire earth in the decentralized deterritorialized sphere of the internet and without the aid of the prophesies of prominent Italian intellectuals. By contrast the centralized bureaucracies of the modern totalitarian states have never been able to sequester “free time” beyond the positive injunction. SAYP is not the state of exclusion-inclusion but rather state of excrescence-involution. The online profile – at least in the context of this review – is precisely one of representation without presentation i.e. Agamben's presentation of Badiou’s concept of “Excrescence” as Representation in a group without Presentation, and which produces an excess/overdetermination of signifiers. "The relationship between membership and inclusion is also marked by a fundamental lack of correspondence, such that inclusion always exceeds membership. [...] The signifier always extends over and beyond the signified." And indeed even the metadata accumulated on me regarding my browsing patterns represents a significant excess over my actual contributions as a "user" in the state of Excrescence. Yet, at exactly the beginning of the attempt to define a profile by these data, the profile paradoxically enters the realm in which it is presented but without representation i.e. involution. The signs of all superfluity of data signifiers cannot begin to describe the signified person who has generated them. As such SAYP is the modern state of Excrescence-Involution (copyright pending). Recent attempts at reconciling these noumena (the ideological core of the social media project – if such a thing exists) threatens to collapse the dichotomy and “return to nature” (meaning, per Agamben, to socially-create for the first time) and replace the current opposition with an undialectical state of “normal membership” (i.e. persons both represented and presented), which, if successful, (and this is not a foregone conclusion), will result of an inversion of public and private life. Private life – being by oneself, bored, staring into space, looking at your phone – unrecorded events since prehistory, now occur publicly as the True Self represented and presented in the Metaverse(tm). Public life – meeting people, talking, a witty phrase – everything recorded in the memory of another, now occurs privately as unrecorded incognito existence and as practice of the unquantifiable.

With as much justification as Agamben’s declaration of the example-exception of the Camp as the epitome of the modern state, I would declare the excrescence-involution of Staring-At-Your-Phone and its threatened (but never actually arriving) collapse into the determined state of Normal Membership to be the fundamental category of relation within the modern state. By the numbers alone I should have him beat, if not by shock value. ( )
  Joe.Olipo | Nov 26, 2022 |
A book I read in full for a paper and did not ever use for that paper. How frustrating! I think that this concept of homo sacer is a little weak, that the enigma of it is what's so attractive about it, but I don't know how far we should try to extend and apply it. I liked best the parts about the homo sacer and the loup-garou, but that's just because I have liked for so long the concept of a werewolf as the fringe of humanity, neither part of it nor entirely out of it. Glad I read it and might use it some day, most likely to pull out and sound perfectly pretentious when I'm feeling the need to distance/impress in mixed company. ( )
  likecymbeline | Apr 1, 2017 |
Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life is the first of seven (and counting) volumes in a large project by contemporary philosopher Giorgio Agamben. (I have previously read the fourth, The Sacrament of Language.) Homo Sacer was first published in 1995, and some have suggested that it was serendipity that the political developments of the early 21st century have been so vulnerable to the tools of analysis that Agamben began to formulate here. Such judgments rest on the dubious view that the events in the US of September 2001, along with the political and governmental reactions to them, were some sort of freak accident alien to the cultivated soil of Western polity.

The point of departure in this book is the antique idea of the homo sacer, a declared outlaw who cannot be "sacrificed," but can be killed without repercussion. Agamben places this figure at the opposite pole from that of the sovereign, in the constitution of the paradoxical "state of exception" -- a concept that he takes from the Nazi jurist and theorist of "political theology" Carl Schmitt, and advances as the principal germ of government, newly exposed in the modern phenomena of "biopolitics" (this latter term from Michel Foucault). Agamben insists -- quite credibly -- that a common biopolitical skeleton lies under the skin of both mass democracies and the notorious totalitarianisms of the 20th century.

Agamben identifies the homo sacer "bandit" (i.e. one under a ban) with "bare life," and this condition is explored through tangent human realities such as subjects of medical experimentation (especially Nazi Versuchspersonen), prisoners condemned to capital punishment, euthanasia candidates, and the "overcomatose," relating these also to the deprecated and disenfranchised classes confined and condemned in totalitarian states. The book is a declared inquiry into the genealogy of the idea of the sanctity of life, and the complicity of this idea with forms of biopolitical oppression and even "thanatopolitical" extermination. It seems a curious oversight that the category of the sovereign fetus is never raised in this survey, given its relationship to the "sanctity of life" in US political rhetoric. (Prohibiting abortion was, of course, a conspicuous biopolitical initiative of Nazi rule.) On a more speculative note, the "ectogene" (a parentless "test tube baby") plays into the nexus of concerns raised in the closing chapters of the book.

One of the chief claims of the book is that human polity should no longer be investigated under the sign of the city, as understood in centuries past, but rather that of the concentration camp. Agamben extends the term to cover all sites of detention, where civil dignities are suspended in consideration of political priorities: refugee quarantine areas, prisons holding aliens to be deported, and so on. Instances of the type have multiplied virally in the last twenty years: the "free speech zones" to divert and suppress street protest in the US, CIA "black sites," and the Homan Square "off-the-books interrogation compound" run by Chicago police are a few that occur to my mind.

Homo Sacer brought ideas together from many other thinkers who have been objects of my attention. Agamben also characterizes the book as an effort to synthesize the political realizations of Hannah Arendt and Michel Foucault (120). Scholars of religion should attend to the theoretical critique bodied forth in the chapter on "The Ambivalence of the Sacred." Thelemites can find ideas worth pondering regarding "pure will" in the Kantian ruminations of the chapter on the "Form of Law." Agamben's work was not a flawless performance, though. Humanistic scholars should probably avoid mathematical or scientific metaphors when they are only superficially familiar with the relevant concepts; he unaccountably wrote "Leyden jar" where he evidently intended "Klein bottle" (37).

Overall, this book was well worth my time, and I expect to read further in the Homo Sacer project, and possibly in some of the secondary literature reacting to Agamben's ideas.
2 vote paradoxosalpha | Mar 6, 2015 |
All the best continental philosophy* books display the best and worst things about continental philosophy: they introduce a profoundly useful concept and make a number of interesting but lesser points about the world in general while they do it. They also needlessly confuse the concept itself, display far too much irrelevant learning (of the "I was reading book x while I was writing book y, therefore book x and y are somehow connected" variety), and make statements that are so over-the-top and ridiculous that any sane reader will only retain her sanity by keeping in mind Adorno's marvelously self-referential claim that all real thought is exaggeration.

According to this implausible statement of mine, Homo Sacer is among the best continental philosophy books. Agamben introduces a very useful and interesting concept by thinking about a)sovereignty, particularly as discussed by Schmitt; b) the figure of homo sacer and the much discussed 'ambiguity of the sacred'; and c) Foucault's concept of biopower. The concept is 'bare life,' which is what the figure of homo sacer is meant to have, what sovereignty rules over, and what Foucault (ait Agamben) was really trying to get at.

This should all be plain sailing, really: the sovereign, Agamben suggests, doesn't so much decide on the exception as decide on the boundaries of legality. The sovereign has the power to turn someone (or some group) into homines sacres, or 'bandits,' or, more making the idea a bit clearer, outlaws. Homo sacer, the outlaw, is both no longer subject to the law- but also no longer protected by it. He can kill you if he wants, but you can kill him without having any legal problem. So the sovereign and the outlaw both stand at the boundaries of human law, civilization etc... When you're in this position, though, you don't really have a full 'life' as such. You aren't a citizen, you aren't a subject- now you're bare life. I doubt it's very nice. This brings with it some interesting points about Heidegger (Dasein as a kind of benign bare life, which is no longer subject to power structures or politics or whatever), anthropological investigations of the sacred and a bunch of other issues in which you might be interested.

Now for the bad stuff:
i) this interesting concept does not allow you to make wildly exaggerated claims like 'economic development turns the entire population of the Third World into bare life,' or 'concentration camps signal the political space of modernity.' Regardless of whether some people are treated as bare life, the vast majority of us remain citizens.

ii) Aristotle's discussion of potentiality in book theta of the Metaphysics has nothing to do with sovereignty, no, nothing at all, and no matter how much fancy footwork you do you will not make them have any relevance to each other. Pindar might have something to do with it, but in a very uninteresting way. Kafka probably has something interesting to say about it, but Agamben doesn't tell us what. Benjamin certainly does, but you could only explain what in a freestanding book length essay on him. All this means that about two thirds of part one of this book are gratuitous and quite irritating. This is a side-effect of the argument-by-outlandish-example method, which also takes up too much space in part three: 'scientists sometimes turn people into lab rats' adds nothing to the concept of bare life.

iii) And finally, I actually have a complaint of substance: despite all the talk of bodies and biopolitics and what-not, Agamben's work is the worst kind of obfuscating idealism. I say this as someone who doesn't mind a little idealism every now and then. But saying 'the Romans conceived of homo sacer in this way... and now we're all homines sacres' leaves out a couple of pretty important *millenia,* through which one probably can't track the figure of homo sacer. What possible effect could this fascinating but arcane legal dispute have today? How is it that such ideas have some immediate impact on people who have never had a politically theoretical idea in their lives?
Agamben could answer, say, 'that's not what I mean; it's not that these ideas have actual worldly effects in the present. It's just a way to think about our world.' That would be okay.
*But*, I'm pretty sure that's not what's going on. He routinely says things like "only a politics that will have learned to take the fundamental biopolitical fracture of the West into account will be able to... put an end to the civil war that divides the peoples and cities of the earth," p 180. I suppose we could dedicate the next twenty years to re-thinking the relation between politics and bare life and sovereignty and so on. We could try to get an absolutely true political theory that steps beyond all of western history and metaphysics, since *only* then will injustice cease. But I'd like to think it isn't *only* when you have a perfect political theory that you can take steps to stop the environmental, political, economic, social and cultural havoc that we seem intent on wreaking.


*yes, I am aware that continental/analytic is a silly distinction, but it holds in this case. ( )
2 vote stillatim | Dec 29, 2013 |
Showing 1-5 of 7 (next | show all)
no reviews | add a review

Belongs to Series

Belongs to Publisher Series

You must log in to edit Common Knowledge data.
For more help see the Common Knowledge help page.
Canonical title
Original title
Alternative titles
Original publication date
People/Characters
Important places
Important events
Related movies
Epigraph
Dedication
First words
Quotations
Last words
Disambiguation notice
Publisher's editors
Blurbers
Original language
Canonical DDC/MDS
Canonical LCC

References to this work on external resources.

Wikipedia in English (1)

The work of Giorgio Agamben, one of Italy's most important and original philosophers, has been based on an uncommon erudition in classical traditions of philosophy and rhetoric, the grammarians of late antiquity, Christian theology, and modern philosophy. Recently, Agamben has begun to direct his thinking to the constitution of the social and to some concrete, ethico-political conclusions concerning the state of society today, and the place of the individual within it. In Homo Sacer, Agamben aims to connect the problem of pure possibility, potentiality, and power with the problem of political and social ethics in a context where the latter has lost its previous religious, metaphysical, and cultural grounding. Taking his cue from Foucault's fragmentary analysis of biopolitics, Agamben probes with great breadth, intensity, and acuteness the covert or implicit presence of an idea of biopolitics in the history of traditional political theory. He argues that from the earliest treatises of political theory, notably in Aristotle's notion of man as a political animal, and throughout the history of Western thinking about sovereignty (whether of the king or the state), a notion of sovereignty as power over "life" is implicit. The reason it remains merely implicit has to do, according to Agamben, with the way the sacred, or the idea of sacrality, becomes indissociable from the idea of sovereignty. Drawing upon Carl Schmitt's idea of the sovereign's status as the exception to the rules he safeguards, and on anthropological research that reveals the close interlinking of the sacred and the taboo, Agamben defines the sacred person as one who can be killed and yet not sacrificed--a paradox he sees as operative in the status of the modern individual living in a system that exerts control over the collective "naked life" of all individuals.

No library descriptions found.

Book description
Haiku summary

Current Discussions

None

Popular covers

Quick Links

Rating

Average: (3.97)
0.5
1 4
1.5
2 5
2.5
3 21
3.5 3
4 29
4.5 1
5 41

Is this you?

Become a LibraryThing Author.

 

About | Contact | Privacy/Terms | Help/FAQs | Blog | Store | APIs | TinyCat | Legacy Libraries | Early Reviewers | Common Knowledge | 204,510,277 books! | Top bar: Always visible